Learn more
These promotions will be applied to this item:
Some promotions may be combined; others are not eligible to be combined with other offers. For details, please see the Terms & Conditions associated with these promotions.
Your Memberships & Subscriptions

Download the free Kindle app and start reading Kindle books instantly on your smartphone, tablet, or computer - no Kindle device required.
Read instantly on your browser with Kindle for Web.
Using your mobile phone camera - scan the code below and download the Kindle app.
Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Kindle Edition
The Nicomachean Ethics is one of Aristotle’s most widely read and influential works. Ideas central to ethics—that happiness is the end of human endeavor, that moral virtue is formed through action and habituation, and that good action requires prudence—found their most powerful proponent in the person medieval scholars simply called “the Philosopher.” Drawing on their intimate knowledge of Aristotle’s thought, Robert C. Bartlett and Susan D. Collins have produced here an English-language translation of the Ethics that is as remarkably faithful to the original as it is graceful in its rendering.
Aristotle is well known for the precision with which he chooses his words, and in this elegant translation his work has found its ideal match. Bartlett and Collins provide copious notes and a glossary providing context and further explanation for students, as well as an introduction and a substantial interpretive essay that sketch central arguments of the work and the seminal place of Aristotle’s Ethics in his political philosophy as a whole.
The Nicomachean Ethics has engaged the serious interest of readers across centuries and civilizations—of peoples ancient, medieval, and modern; pagan, Christian, Muslim, and Jewish—and this new edition will take its place as the standard English-language translation.
Customers who bought this item also bought
Editorial Reviews
Review
“This is the only English translation of the Ethics for those who want or need to know precisely, not just roughly, what Aristotle says. Readers now can behold the splendor of his conception of moral virtue and engage with its subtleties as well. The translation is accompanied by excellent notes, an interpretive essay, indices, and a highly useful glossary.”
-- Harvey C. Mansfield, Harvard University“Bartlett and Collins’s translation of the Nicomachean Ethics is the best in English that I have read. It nicely couples a consistent faithfulness to Aristotle’s Greek with a high degree of readability. This will be a real service to scholars and students.”
-- Gerald M. Mara, Georgetown University“[This volume] is much more than a translation. The translators, Robert C. Bartlett . . . and Susan D. Collins . . . have provided helpful aids. . . . [They have] supplied an informative introduction, as well as ‘A Note on the Translation,’ a bibliography and an outline of the work. All this precedes the main text. Afterward comes a brief ‘Overview of the Moral Virtues and Vices,’ a very extensive and invaluable glossary, a list of ‘Key Greek Terms,’ an index of proper names and at last a detailed ‘general index.’ Together these bring the original text within the compass of every intelligent reader. . . . Brilliant and readable.”
-- Harry V. Jaffa ― New York Times Book Review“There are several good editions of the Nicomachean Ethics currently available, but the Bartlett and Collins version is superior in several decisive respects—philological, philosophical, and pedagogical. The translation itself is consistently faithful to the text without lapsing into obscurity or awkwardness, with lots of helpful discussion (in just the right number of notes conveniently placed at the bottom of the page) of alternative possibilities at key points. Best of all, the thoughtful and well-crafted surrounding material—notes, glossary, introduction, and interpretive essay—supplies a marvelous guide to Aristotle’s unique way of presenting the central questions of ethics and politics. This is the version I will use when next I teach the Nicomachean Ethics.”
-- Stephen G. Salkever, Bryn Mawr College“This translation will easily be the best available English version of the Nicomachean Ethics.”
-- Michael Davis, Sarah Lawrence College“[A] readable, careful, and unusually reliable translation.”
-- E. M. Macierowski ― ChoiceAbout the Author
Excerpt. © Reprinted by permission. All rights reserved.
ARISTOTLE'S Nicomachean Ethics
By ROBERT C. BARTLETT SUSAN D. COLLINSThe University of Chicago Press
Copyright © 2011 The University of ChicagoAll right reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-226-02674-9
Contents
Introduction................................................viiA Note on the Translation...................................xvBibliography................................................xixOutline of the Nicomachean Ethics...........................xxiiiBOOK 1......................................................1BOOK 2......................................................26BOOK 3......................................................42BOOK 4......................................................67BOOK 5......................................................90BOOK 6......................................................115BOOK 7......................................................135BOOK 8......................................................163BOOK 9......................................................188BOOK 10.....................................................210Interpretive Essay..........................................237Overview of the Moral Virtues and Vices.....................303Glossary: English-Greek.....................................305Key Greek Terms.............................................317Index of Proper Names.......................................321General Index...............................................323Chapter One
CHAPTER ONEEvery art and every inquiry, and similarly every action as well as choice, is held to aim at some good. Hence people have nobly declared that the good is that at which all things aim. But there appears to be a certain difference among the ends: some ends are activities, others are certain works apart from the activities themselves, and in those cases in which there are certain ends apart from the actions, the works are naturally better than the activities.
Now, since there are many actions, arts, and sciences, the ends too are many: of medicine, the end is health; of shipbuilding, a ship; of generalship, victory; of household management, wealth. And in all things of this sort that fall under some one capacity—for just as bridle making and such other arts as concern equestrian gear fall under horsemanship, while this art and every action related to warfare fall under generalship, so in the same manner, some arts fall under one capacity, others under another—in all of them, the ends of the architectonic ones are more choice-worthy than all those that fall under them, for these latter are pursued for the sake of the former. And it makes no difference at all whether the ends of the actions are the activities themselves or something else apart from these, as in the sciences mentioned.
CHAPTER TWO
If, therefore, there is some end of our actions that we wish for on account of itself, the rest being things we wish for on account of this end, and if we do not choose all things on account of something else—for in this way the process will go on infinitely such that the longing involved is empty and pointless—clearly this would be the good, that is, the best. And with a view to our life, then, is not the knowledge of this good of great weight, and would we not, like archers in possession of a target, better hit on what is needed? If this is so, then one must try to grasp, in outline at least, whatever it is and to which of the sciences or capacities it belongs.
But it might be held to belong to the most authoritative and most architectonic one, and such appears to be the political art. For it ordains what sciences there must be in cities and what kinds each person in turn must learn and up to what point. We also see that even the most honored capacities—for example, generalship, household management, rhetoric—fall under the political art. Because it makes use of the remaining sciences and, further, because it legislates what one ought to do and what to abstain from, its end would encompass those of the others, with the result that this would be the human good. For even if this is the same thing for an individual and a city, to secure and preserve the good of the city appears to be something greater and more complete: the good of the individual by himself is certainly desirable enough, but that of a nation and of cities is nobler and more divine.
The inquiry, then, aims at these things, since it is a sort of political inquiry.
CHAPTER THREE
The inquiry would be adequately made if it should attain the clarity that accords with the subject matter. For one should not seek out precision in all arguments alike, just as one should not do so in the products of craftsmanship either. The noble things and the just things, which the political art examines, admit of much dispute and variability, such that they are held to exist by law alone and not by nature. And even the good things admit of some such variability on account of the harm that befalls many people as a result of them: it has happened that some have been destroyed on account of their wealth, others on account of their courage.
It would certainly be desirable enough, then, if one who speaks about and on the basis of such things demonstrate the truth roughly and in outline, and if, in speaking about and on the basis of things that are for the most part so, one draw conclusions of that sort as well. Indeed, in the same manner one must also accept each of the points being made. For it belongs to an educated person to seek out precision in each genus to the extent that the nature of the matter allows: to accept persuasive speech from a skilled mathematician appears comparable to demanding demonstrations from a skilled rhetorician. Each person judges nobly the things he knows, and of these he is a good judge. He is a good judge of a particular thing, therefore, if he has been educated with a view to it, but is a good judge simply if he has been educated about everything. Hence of the political art, a young person is not an appropriate student, for he is inexperienced in the actions pertaining to life, and the arguments are based on these actions and concern them.
Further, because he is disposed to follow the passions, he will listen pointlessly and unprofitably, since the end involved is not knowledge but action. And it makes no difference at all whether he is young in age or immature in character: the deficiency is not related to time but instead arises on account of living in accord with passion and pursuing each passion in turn. For to people of that sort, just as to those lacking self-restraint, knowledge is without benefit. But to those who fashion their longings in accord with reason and act accordingly, knowing about these things would be of great profit.
About the student, and how one ought to accept [what is being said], and what it is that we propose, let these things stand as a prelude.
CHAPTER FOUR
Now, let us pick up again and—since all knowledge and every choice have some good as the object of their longing—let us state what it is that we say the political art aims at and what the highest of all the goods related to action is. As for its name, then, it is pretty much agreed on by most people; for both the many and the refined say that it is happiness, and they suppose that living well and acting well are the same thing as being happy. But as for what happiness is, they disagree, and the many do not give a response similar to that of the wise. The former respond that it is something obvious and manifest, such as pleasure or wealth or honor, some saying it is one thing, others another. Oft en one and the same person responds differently, for when he is sick, it is health; when poor, wealth. And when they are aware of their own ignorance, they wonder at those who say something that is great and beyond them. Certain others, in addition, used to suppose that the good is something else, by itself, apart from these many good things, which is also the cause of their all being good.
Now, to examine thoroughly all these opinions is perhaps rather pointless; those opinions that are especially prevalent or are held to have a certain reason to them will suffice. But let it not escape our notice that there is a difference between the arguments that proceed from the principles and those that proceed to the principles. For Plato too used to raise this perplexity well and investigate it, whether the path is going from the principles or to the principles, just as on a racecourse one can proceed from the judges to the finish line or back again. One must begin from what is known, but this has a twofold meaning: there are things known to us, on the one hand, and things known simply, on the other. Perhaps it is necessary for us, at least, to begin from the things known to us. Hence he who will listen adequately to the noble things and the just things, and to the political things generally, must be brought up nobly by means of habituation. For the "that" is a principle, and if this should be sufficiently apparent, there will be no need of the "why" in addition, and a person of the sort indicated has or would easily get hold of principles. As for him to whom neither of these is available, let him listen to the words of Hesiod:
This one is altogether best who himself understands all things
But good in his turn too is he who obeys one who speaks well. But he who neither himself understands nor, in listening to another, Takes this to heart, he is a useless man.
CHAPTER FIVE
Let us speak from the point where we digressed. For on the basis of the lives they lead, the many and crudest seem to suppose, not unreasonably, that the good and happiness are pleasure. And thus they cherish the life of enjoyment. For the especially prominent ways of life are three: the one just mentioned, the political, and, third, the contemplative.
Now, in choosing a life of fatted cattle, the many appear altogether slavish; but they attain a hearing, because many people in positions of authority experience passions like those of Sardanapallus. The refined and active, on the other hand, choose honor, for this is pretty much the end of the political life. But it appears to be more superficial than what is being sought, for honor seems to reside more with those who bestow it than with him who receives it; and we divine that the good is something of one's own and a thing not easily taken away. Further, people seem to pursue honor so that they may be convinced that they themselves are good; at any rate, they seek to be honored by the prudent, among those to whom they are known, and for their virtue. It is clear, then, that in the case of these people at least, virtue is superior.
And perhaps someone might in fact suppose that virtue is to a greater degree the end of the political life. Yet it too appears to be rather incomplete. For it seems to be possible for someone to possess virtue even while asleep or while being inactive throughout life and, in addition to these, while suffering badly and undergoing the greatest misfortunes. But no one would deem happy somebody living in this way, unless he were defending a thesis. But enough about these things: they have been spoken about adequately also in the circulated writings.
Third is the contemplative life, about which we will make an investigation in what will follow.
The moneymaking life is characterized by a certain constraint, and it is clear that wealth is not the good being sought, for it is a useful thing and for the sake of something else. Thus someone might suppose that the previously mentioned things are ends to a greater degree than is money, for at least they are cherished for their own sakes. But they do not appear to be ends either, and many arguments have been widely distributed in opposition to them. So let these things be dismissed.
CHAPTER SIX
As for the universal [good], perhaps it is better to examine it and to go through the perplexities involved in the ways it is spoken of, although undertaking such an inquiry is arduous, because the men who introduced the forms are dear. But perhaps it might be held to be better, and in fact to be obligatory, at least for the sake of preserving the truth, to do away with even one's own things, especially for those who are philosophers. For although both are dear, it is a pious thing to honor the truth first.
Now, those who conveyed this opinion did not make ideas pertain to those cases in which they spoke of the prior and posterior; hence they did not set up an idea of numbers either. But the good is spoken of in relation to what something is, and in relation to what sort of thing it is, and as regards its relation to something; but that which is the thing in itself—that is, the being—is prior by nature to any relation it has (for this is like an off shoot and accident of the being). As a result, there would not be any common idea pertaining to these things.
And further, the good is spoken of in as many ways as is the term is—for the good is spoken of in relation to what something is (for example, the god and intellect); as for what sort of thing something is, the good is spoken of as the virtues; as for how much something is, it is spoken of as the measured amount; in its relation to something, as what is useful; as regards time, as the opportune moment; as regards place, as the [right] location; and other things of this sort. [Since all this is so,] it is clear that the good would not be something common, universal, and one. For if that were the case, it would not be spoken of in all the categories but in one alone.
And further, since there is a single science of things that pertain to a single idea, there would also be some single science of all the good things. But as things stand, there are many sciences even of things that fall under a single category—for example, the opportune moment: in war, it is generalship, in illness, medicine; and in the case of the measured amount of nourishment, on the one hand, it is medicine, but in that of physical exertions, on the other, it is gymnastic training.
But someone might be perplexed as to whatever they mean by "thing-as-such," if in fact the very same account of human being pertains both to "human being-as-such" and to a given human being. For in the respect in which each is a human being, they will not differ at all. And if this is so, [then neither the good-as-such nor a good thing will differ] in the respect in which each is good. Moreover, the good will not be good to a greater degree by being eternal either, if in fact whiteness that lasts a long time will not be whiter than that which lasts only a day.
The Pythagoreans seem to speak more persuasively about it by positing the One in the column of the goods, and it is indeed they whom Speusippus seems to follow. But about these things let there be another argument.
A certain dispute over the points stated begins to appear, because the arguments made [by the proponents of the forms] do not concern every good: things pursued and cherished by themselves are spoken of in reference to a single form, but what produces these (or in some way preserves them or prevents their contraries) is spoken of as being good on account of the former sorts of goods and in a different manner. It is clear, then, that the good things would be spoken of in two senses: those that are good in themselves, others that are good on account of these.
Separating the things good in themselves from those that are advantageous, then, let us examine whether the former are spoken of in reference to a single idea. What sorts of things might someone posit as being good in themselves? Is it so many things as are in fact pursued for themselves alone—for example, exercising prudence and seeing, as well as certain pleasures and honors? For even if we pursue these on account of something else as well, nonetheless one might posit them as being among the things that are good in themselves. Or is nothing good in itself except the idea? The result will be that the form [abstracted from all individual good things] is pointless. But if in fact these things [that is, exercising prudence, seeing, and the like] are among the things good in themselves, the definition of the good will need to manifest itself as the same in all cases, just as the definition of whiteness is the same in the case of snow and in that of white lead. But the definitions of honor, prudence, and pleasure are distinct and differ in the very respect in which they are goods. It is not the case, therefore, that the good is something common in reference to a single idea.
But how indeed are they spoken of [as good]? For they are not like things that share the same name by chance. Is it by dint of their stemming from one thing or because they all contribute to one thing? Or is it more that they are such by analogy? For as there is sight in the body, so there is intellect in the soul, and indeed one thing in one thing, another in another. But perhaps we ought to leave these considerations be for now: to be very precise about them would be more appropriate to another philosophy. The case is similar with the idea as well: even if there is some one good thing that is predicated [of things] in common, or there is some separate thing, itself by itself, it is clear that it would not be subject to action or capable of being possessed by a human being. But it is just some such thing that is now being sought.
Perhaps someone might be of the opinion that it is better to be familiar with it, with a view to those goods that can be possessed and are subject to action. By having this [universal good] as a sort of model, we will to a greater degree know also the things that are good for us; and if we know them, we will hit on them. Now, the argument has a certain persuasiveness, but it seems to be inconsistent with the sciences. For although all sciences aim at some good and seek out what is lacking, they pass over knowledge of the good itself. And yet it is not reasonable for all craftsmen to be ignorant of so great an aid and not even to seek it out.
(Continues...)
Excerpted from ARISTOTLE'S Nicomachean Ethicsby ROBERT C. BARTLETT SUSAN D. COLLINS Copyright © 2011 by The University of Chicago. Excerpted by permission of The University of Chicago Press. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.
Product details
- ASIN : B006J8QAT2
- Publisher : University of Chicago Press (May 1, 2011)
- Publication date : May 1, 2011
- Language : English
- File size : 1.4 MB
- Text-to-Speech : Enabled
- Screen Reader : Supported
- Enhanced typesetting : Enabled
- X-Ray : Enabled
- Word Wise : Enabled
- Print length : 513 pages
- Best Sellers Rank: #233,331 in Kindle Store (See Top 100 in Kindle Store)
- #210 in Ethics & Morality
- #303 in Political Science (Kindle Store)
- #787 in Philosophy of Ethics & Morality
- Customer Reviews:
About the authors
Robert C. Bartlett is the Behrakis Professor in Hellenic Political Studies, Department of Political Science, Boston College, where he has served since 2010.
His main area of study is classical political philosophy, and in particular Xenophon, Plato, Thucydides, and Aristotle.
A graduate of the University of Toronto, Robert Bartlett holds a Master's in Classics and Ph.D. in Political Science from Boston College. Before teaching at Boston College, he held the Blank Distinguished Teaching Chair at Emory University in Atlanta, GA.
He is the author or editor of nine books and many scholarly articles.
Discover more of the author’s books, see similar authors, read book recommendations and more.
Aristotle (/ˈærɪˌstɒtəl/; Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης [aristotélɛːs], Aristotélēs; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and scientist born in the city of Stagira, Chalkidice, on the northern periphery of Classical Greece. His father, Nicomachus, died when Aristotle was a child, whereafter Proxenus of Atarneus became his guardian. At eighteen, he joined Plato's Academy in Athens and remained there until the age of thirty-seven (c. 347 BC). His writings cover many subjects – including physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics, poetry, theater, music, rhetoric, linguistics, politics and government – and constitute the first comprehensive system of Western philosophy. Shortly after Plato died, Aristotle left Athens and, at the request of Philip of Macedon, tutored Alexander the Great starting from 343 BC. According to the Encyclopædia Britannica, "Aristotle was the first genuine scientist in history ... [and] every scientist is in his debt."
Teaching Alexander the Great gave Aristotle many opportunities and an abundance of supplies. He established a library in the Lyceum which aided in the production of many of his hundreds of books. The fact that Aristotle was a pupil of Plato contributed to his former views of Platonism, but, following Plato's death, Aristotle immersed himself in empirical studies and shifted from Platonism to empiricism. He believed all peoples' concepts and all of their knowledge was ultimately based on perception. Aristotle's views on natural sciences represent the groundwork underlying many of his works.
Aristotle's views on physical science profoundly shaped medieval scholarship. Their influence extended into the Renaissance and were not replaced systematically until the Enlightenment and theories such as classical mechanics. Some of Aristotle's zoological observations, such as on the hectocotyl (reproductive) arm of the octopus, were not confirmed or refuted until the 19th century. His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, which was incorporated in the late 19th century into modern formal logic.
In metaphysics, Aristotelianism profoundly influenced Judeo-Islamic philosophical and theological thought during the Middle Ages and continues to influence Christian theology, especially the scholastic tradition of the Catholic Church. Aristotle was well known among medieval Muslim intellectuals and revered as "The First Teacher" (Arabic: المعلم الأول).
His ethics, though always influential, gained renewed interest with the modern advent of virtue ethics. All aspects of Aristotle's philosophy continue to be the object of active academic study today. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues – Cicero described his literary style as "a river of gold" – it is thought that only around a third of his original output has survived.
Bio from Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia. Photo by Copy of Lysippus (Jastrow (2006)) [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons.
Customer reviews
Customer Reviews, including Product Star Ratings help customers to learn more about the product and decide whether it is the right product for them.
To calculate the overall star rating and percentage breakdown by star, we don’t use a simple average. Instead, our system considers things like how recent a review is and if the reviewer bought the item on Amazon. It also analyzed reviews to verify trustworthiness.
Learn more how customers reviews work on AmazonCustomers say
Customers find the book very readable and consider it a true classic, with one noting how it brings readers closer to the text. Moreover, the encyclopedia content receives positive feedback, with one customer highlighting the wonderful notes about various terms. However, the translation quality receives mixed reviews, with some praising it while others find it extremely difficult to read in some places.
AI-generated from the text of customer reviews
Select to learn more
Customers find the book easy to read and worth the effort, with one customer noting how it brings readers closer to the text.
"...can be dense at times, the wisdom in these pages makes it worth the effort. A true classic!" Read more
"...that the reader is brought closer to the text, and therefore to the meaning of the author, and not estranged from it by excessive pandering to the..." Read more
"Enjoyed reading and understanding different perspectives. Strongly recommend." Read more
"...Aristotle is difficult, but this reads really well. And all the notes and other things make the book much easier to understand. Highly recommended!" Read more
Customers appreciate the encyclopedia content of the book, which includes interpretative essays, wonderful notes about various terms, and informative footnotes, with one customer noting the helpful list of principles to live by.
"...Ethics is a must-read for anyone interested in philosophy, morality, or personal growth...." Read more
"...rethinking of how to translate Aristotle into English, and so many useful features such as footnotes (not tiresome endnotes), a glossary,..." Read more
"...to Aristotle and not only place him in his historical and philosophical context but also discuss his continued influence even into the 21st Century...." Read more
"Enjoyed reading and understanding different perspectives. Strongly recommend." Read more
Customers appreciate the classic content of the book, describing it as a true masterpiece and fundamental western classic.
"...A true classic!" Read more
"...This is one of the fundamental western classics. As for the book itself, it arrived with the entire back cover dirty/stained (see photo)...." Read more
"Masterpiece! Good for all who reflect on the big questions! Not a light read." Read more
"Good edition" Read more
Customers have mixed opinions about the translation of the book, with some finding it excellent while others report that it is extremely difficult to read in some places.
"...to their introduction, Bartlett and Collins write a helpful Note On Translation that provides insight into their literal translation approach...." Read more
"I'm in the process of reading this wonderful book now. The translations are great but it will be difficult sometimes if you aren't an avid reader of..." Read more
"...While the language can be dense at times, the wisdom in these pages makes it worth the effort. A true classic!" Read more
"...It is a fantastic translation with wonderful notes about a variety of terms and the meaning of certain phrases that Aristotle uses...." Read more
Reviews with images

Great read
Top reviews from the United States
There was a problem filtering reviews. Please reload the page.
- Reviewed in the United States on February 20, 2025Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics is a must-read for anyone interested in philosophy, morality, or personal growth. His insights on virtue, happiness, and the good life are as relevant today as they were centuries ago. While the language can be dense at times, the wisdom in these pages makes it worth the effort. A true classic!
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics is a must-read for anyone interested in philosophy, morality, or personal growth. His insights on virtue, happiness, and the good life are as relevant today as they were centuries ago. While the language can be dense at times, the wisdom in these pages makes it worth the effort. A true classic!
Images in this review
- Reviewed in the United States on June 4, 2011Bartlett and Collins have penned what now must be considered the translation of choice into English of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics.
The best review I have so far read of it is "Code of the Gentleman" by Diana Schaub in The Claremont Review of Books with the response of the authors.
There are so many felicities in their rethinking of how to translate Aristotle into English, and so many useful features such as footnotes (not tiresome endnotes), a glossary, interpretative essay, detailed indices etc., that the reader is brought closer to the text, and therefore to the meaning of the author, and not estranged from it by excessive pandering to the limitations of careless readers who do not like to have to think long and hard to get to the truth about things, especially naturally contentious human things like `morality'.
This translation surpasses those by Sachs, Broadie and Rowe, Irwin, Ostwald, and Ross (the superior literary, but not literal translation) which are still useful to consult especially for their critical apparatus and alternative readings of key terms.
Alas, certain significant words do not have footnotes or glossary entries, such as `inquiry/investigation' which they use to translate methodos - literally "the way after" or "the way towards" or "the way of proceeding" especially to the truth about the things human - philosophy. A detailed analytical outline would have been helpful. And, perhaps the size of the font could have been a bit larger in kindness to older eyes.
This translation is also the superior twin to Carnes Lord's translation of "Aristotle The Politics" from the same stable, The University of Chicago Press.
The other most useful pair of literal translations of Aristotle's "philosophy of things human" would be Joe Sachs, "Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics" and Peter L. Phillips Simpson's, "The Politics of Aristotle". The appendix to the Politics is the "Poetics" of which Seth Benardete's translation is the superior literal and scholarly translation, perhaps followed by Joe Sachs. The other work in Aristotle's quartet (or trilogy if one accepts the Poetics as a form of appendix to the Politics) is the "Rhetoric" which Bartlett has now also translated literally with a useful interpretive essay, glossary and notes.
- Reviewed in the United States on April 7, 2020I read this English edition of Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics as part of my journey through the Western canon. My rating and this review are not of Aristotle himself, but of this English edition.
First, Bartlett and Collins write an excellent short introduction to Aristotle and not only place him in his historical and philosophical context but also discuss his continued influence even into the 21st Century. Their introduction addresses how a post-modern steeped in moral relativism can still benefit from the absolute moral values presented by Aristotle. In addition to their introduction, Bartlett and Collins write a helpful Note On Translation that provides insight into their literal translation approach. In my study of ancient languages (Hebrew, Koine Greek, and Latin), I have come to prefer this approach myself.
Second, Bartlett and Collins provide the reader with a superb English translation. Clear. Crisp. Accessible.
Third, I love the informative footnotes from Bartlett and Collins. The notes provide helpful historical, social, and literary context, they give insight into the underlying Greek terms Aristotle uses, and they provide visibility to manuscript variants. And, they're footnotes and not end notes!
Fourth, I read through most of their interpretive essay (I read parts of it after I read each chapter in the Ethics), but honestly I didn't find it that helpful. I'd recommend skipping the interpretive essay except when it deals with chapters 6 and 7 of the Ethics.
Overall, great English edition of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. 5-out-of-5 stars.
- Reviewed in the United States on October 22, 2024Enjoyed reading and understanding different perspectives. Strongly recommend.
- Reviewed in the United States on September 14, 2022While I knew who Aristotle was I had never read any of his works. Extremely difficult to read in some places yet surprisingly easy in others. I think Aristotle himself wasn’t quite sure of what he was saying. He also contradicts himself in some places. The translators did a good job of sorting these discrepancies out.
Overall I am glad I read while I do not entirely agree with him, I have a better understanding of current ethics.
- Reviewed in the United States on December 2, 2023This is the best version of the book I've come across. Aristotle is difficult, but this reads really well. And all the notes and other things make the book much easier to understand. Highly recommended!
- Reviewed in the United States on July 21, 2024A foundational work of western civilization
- Reviewed in the United States on June 10, 2015A perfect book, obviously, so the translation's all I'm going to talk about.
I think the 'literalness' of the translation is a bit overstated, though it seems to be the best one available (better than Reeve's recent translation, certainly.) But expect a manifestly strong ‘Straussian’ influence, and this goes too for the 65 page interpretive essay accompanying the text. The essay is thought provoking if sometimes pretty under-motivated in its use of evidence; it doesn't seem like Straussianism is quite as conducive to Aristotle as to Plato (hence, one would think, Strauss's relative dearth of commentaries on the former—not that it stops his dsiciples).
Anyway, the assimilation of Aristotelian terms of art in the body of the translation to the terms employed in Bloom's translation of Plato's Republic is both interesting and possibly misleading. Nevertheless, this seems to me to be the best translation available.
Top reviews from other countries
- MALVIOUSReviewed in Canada on June 5, 2023
5.0 out of 5 stars Very interesting read
Needed to buy it for university and I really enjoyed reading it!
Would totally recommend!
- STReviewed in the United Kingdom on January 25, 2014
5.0 out of 5 stars Higher knowledge
This is why the Ellanoi (that we mistakenly call "greeks" today) conquered the world with their culture. When everybody else was still living in little mud huts, the Ellanoi philosophers were talking about ethics and higher knowledge. This book is a fine example of an extraordinary civilization that still shines bright all over the world.
- Amazon CustomerReviewed in the United Kingdom on November 19, 2016
5.0 out of 5 stars Five Stars
Excellent copy, very good
- william pocockReviewed in Canada on February 10, 2018
5.0 out of 5 stars The interpretive essay is most useful. This is quite the gem
I really couldn't ask for more in a thoughtful, diligent translation. Fives stars for what it set out to be. I'm using this as an occasional reference for my own abridgement of the Ross version. The interpretive essay is most useful. This is quite the gem, even if reading Aristotle as he wished to be understood is a too often painful slog. But there's real, essential, foundational ideas and arguments therein. That's why I'm doing the abridgement to separate the wheat from the chaff. Thanks, guys! Super scholarly work, and much appreciated to compare with my own take on the material.
- Matthew WoodsReviewed in Canada on May 21, 2018
5.0 out of 5 stars The book itself is great.
I absolutely adore this book. Aesthetically it is amazing and the translation is great and the notes/annotations really help. If you're going to read any version of this book make it this one. Since this book is in the public domain the main reason to purchase it, at least in my view, are on aesthetic grounds and this book is exceedingly well in that category. From the quality of the cover to the quality of the paper used for the book cover... A+ all around.
One person found this helpfulReport