Learn more
These promotions will be applied to this item:
Some promotions may be combined; others are not eligible to be combined with other offers. For details, please see the Terms & Conditions associated with these promotions.
Audiobook Price: $15.04$15.04
Save: $7.55$7.55 (50%)
- Highlight, take notes, and search in the book
- In this edition, page numbers are just like the physical edition
Your Memberships & Subscriptions

Download the free Kindle app and start reading Kindle books instantly on your smartphone, tablet, or computer - no Kindle device required.
Read instantly on your browser with Kindle for Web.
Using your mobile phone camera - scan the code below and download the Kindle app.
Beyond Weird: Why Everything You Thought You Knew about Quantum Physics Is Different First Edition, Kindle Edition
“Anyone who is not shocked by quantum theory has not understood it.” Since Niels Bohr said this many years ago, quantum mechanics has only been getting more shocking. We now realize that it’s not really telling us that “weird” things happen out of sight, on the tiniest level, in the atomic world: rather, everything is quantum. But if quantum mechanics is correct, what seems obvious and right in our everyday world is built on foundations that don’t seem obvious or right at all—or even possible.
An exhilarating tour of the contemporary quantum landscape, Beyond Weird is a book about what quantum physics really means—and what it doesn’t. Philip Ball offers an up-to-date, accessible account of the quest to come to grips with the most fundamental theory of physical reality, and to explain how its counterintuitive principles underpin the world we experience. Over the past decade it’s become clear that quantum physics is less a theory about particles and waves, uncertainty and fuzziness, than a theory about information and knowledge—about what can be known, and how we can know it. Discoveries and experiments over the past few decades have called into question the meanings and limits of space and time, cause and effect, and, ultimately, of knowledge itself. The quantum world Ball shows us isn’t a different world. It is our world, and if anything deserves to be called “weird,” it’s us.
“Weighs up the competing interpretations, and the misconceptions, that have attached themselves to quantum theory in its 100-year history. . . . [A] laudable achievement.”—Sunday Times
“Ball is one of the finest contemporary writers about science. . . . His prose is a pleasure to read.”—Wall Street Journal
- ISBN-13978-0226594989
- EditionFirst
- PublisherThe University of Chicago Press
- Publication dateOctober 18, 2018
- LanguageEnglish
- File size9.3 MB
Kindle E-Readers
- Kindle Paperwhite
- Kindle Paperwhite (5th Generation)
- Kindle Paperwhite (11th Generation)
- Kindle Touch
- Kindle Scribe, 1st generation (2024 release)
- All New Kindle E-reader
- Kindle Scribe (1st Generation)
- Kindle (10th Generation)
- Kindle
- Kindle Voyage
- Kindle Paperwhite (10th Generation)
- Kindle Oasis (9th Generation)
- Kindle Oasis
- Kindle Paperwhite (12th Generation)
- All New Kindle E-reader (11th Generation)
- Kindle Oasis (10th Generation)
- All new Kindle paperwhite
Fire Tablets
Customers who bought this item also bought
Editorial Reviews
Review
“Ball’s gorgeously lucid text takes us to the edge of contemporary theorizing about the foundations of quantum mechanics. Beyond Weird is easily the best book I’ve read on the subject.” -- Washington Post
“It would be easy to think 'Surely we don't need another book on quantum physics.' There are loads of them. . . . Don't be fooled, though - because in Beyond Weird, Philip Ball has done something rare in my experience. . .it makes an attempt not to describe quantum physics, but to explain why it is the way it is.” ― PopScience Books
“An excellent account of modern quantum theory and the efforts being made to harness its effects.” ― The Spectator
"The intention of Beyond Weird, though, is not simply to provide a dummy’s guide to the theory, but to explore its underlying meaning. We know that the equations work, but what sort of world do they really represent? To tackle the question, he weighs up the competing interpretations, and the misconceptions, that have attached themselves to quantum theory in its 100-year history, finishing with more recent attempts to rebuild the theory 'from scratch', and new ideas that offer tantalising glimpses beyond. . . . [A] laudable achievement."
― Sunday Times"This is the book on quantum mechanics that I wish I’d written, but I’m really glad I read. Philip Ball really encapsulates the sheer mystery of quantum mechanics so well." -- Jim Al-Khalili ― BBC Science Focus
"Philip Ball is one of the finest contemporary writers about science. . . . His prose is a pleasure to read." ― Wall Street Journal
"If so great a physicist as Richard Feynman once claimed that 'nobody understands quantum mechanics,' what hope do we laypeople have? Luckily, Philip Ball, a freelance writer (formerly of Nature magazine) who has published widely on the history of science, tackles the subject in a user-friendly yet thorough introduction. . . . Replacing 'obscure terminology' with accessible ideas and drawings, Ball makes would-be physicists of us all."
― Foreword Review
"Ball . . . asks lots of questions, including rhetorical ones, and uses words like 'we' and 'let's' to turn readers into collaborators. The tone is reassuring; he never talks down to nonscientists. Instead, he invites them to join in exploring this 'new and unfamiliar logic' in which what we understand and how we measure something has an effect on what we observe. Replacing 'obscure terminology' with accessible ideas and drawings, Ball makes would-be physicists of us all." ― Foreword Reviews
Review
About the Author
Philip Ball worked for over twenty years as an editor for Nature, writes regularly in the scientific and popular media, and has authored many books on the interactions of the sciences, the arts, and the wider culture. His most recent books include Patterns in Nature, Invisible, and Serving the Reich. He lives in London.
Excerpt. © Reprinted by permission. All rights reserved.
Beyond Weird
Why Everything You Thought You Knew about Quantum Physics is Different
By Philip BallThe University of Chicago Press
Copyright © 2018 Philip BallAll rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-226-55838-7
CHAPTER 1
No one can say what
quantum mechanics means (and this is a book about it)
Richard Feynman said that in 1965. In the same year he was awarded the Nobel Prize in Physics, for his work on quantum mechanics.
In case we didn't get the point, Feynman drove it home in his artful Everyman style. 'I was born not understanding quantum mechanics,' he exclaimed merrily, '[and] I still don't understand quantum mechanics!' Here was the man who had just been anointed one of the foremost experts on the topic, declaring his ignorance of it.
What hope was there, then, for the rest of us?
Feynman's much-quoted words help to seal the reputation of quantum mechanics as one of the most obscure and difficult subjects in all of science. Quantum mechanics has become symbolic of 'impenetrable science', in the same way that the name of Albert Einstein (who played a key role in its inception) acts as shorthand for scientific genius.
Feynman clearly didn't mean that he couldn't do quantum theory. He meant that this was all he could do. He could work through the math just fine – he invented some of it, after all. That wasn't the problem. Sure, there's no point in pretending that the math is easy, and if you never got on with numbers then a career in quantum mechanics isn't for you. But neither, in that case, would be a career in fluid mechanics, population dynamics, or economics, which are equally inscrutable to the numerically challenged.
No, the equations aren't why quantum mechanics is perceived to be so hard. It's the ideas. We just can't get our heads around them. Neither could Richard Feynman.
His failure, Feynman admitted, was to understand what the math was saying. It provided numbers: predictions of quantities that could be tested against experiments, and which invariably survived those tests. But Feynman couldn't figure out what these numbers and equations were really about: what they said about the 'real world'.
One view is that they don't say anything about the 'real world'. They're just fantastically useful machinery, a kind of black box that we can use, very reliably, to do science and engineering. Another view is that the notion of a 'real world' beyond the math is meaningless, and we shouldn't waste our time thinking about it. Or perhaps we haven't yet found the right math to answer questions about the world it purports to describe. Or maybe, it's sometimes said, the math tells us that 'everything that can happen does happen' – whatever that means.
This is a book about what quantum math really means. Happily, we can explore that question without having to look very deeply into the math itself. Even what little I've included here can, if you prefer, be gingerly set aside.
I am not saying that this book is going to give you the answer. We don't have an answer. (Some people do have an answer, but only in the sense that some people have the Bible: their truth rests on faith, not proof.) We do, however, now have better questions than we did when Feynman admitted his ignorance, and that counts for a lot.
What we can say is that the narrative of quantum mechanics – at least among those who think most deeply about its meaning – has changed in remarkable ways since the end of the twentieth century. Quantum theory has revolutionized our concept of atoms, molecules, light and their interactions, but that transformation didn't happen abruptly and in some ways it is still happening now. It began in the early 1900s and it had a workable set of equations and ideas by the late 1920s. Only since the 1960s, however, have we begun to glimpse what is most fundamental and important about the theory, and some of the crucial experiments have been feasible only from the 1980s. Several of them have been performed in the twenty-first century. Even today we are still trying to get to grips with the central ideas, and are still testing their limits. If what we truly want is a theory that is well understood rather than simply one that does a good job at calculating numbers, then we still don't really have a quantum theory.
This book aims to give a sense of the current best guesses about what that real quantum theory might look like, if it existed. It rather seems as though such a theory would unsettle most if not all we take for granted about the deep fabric of the world, which appears to be a far stranger and more challenging place than we had previously envisaged. It is not a place where different physical rules apply, so much as a place where we are forced to rethink our ideas about what we mean by a physical world and what we think we are doing when we attempt to find out about it.
In surveying these new perspectives, I want to insist on two things that have emerged from the modern renaissance – the word is fully warranted – in investigations of the foundations of quantum mechanics.
First, what is all too frequently described as the weirdness of quantum physics is not a true oddity of the quantum world but comes from our (understandably) contorted attempts to find pictures for visualizing it or stories to tell about it. Quantum physics defies intuition, but we do it an injustice by calling that circumstance 'weird'.
Second – and worse – this 'weirdness' trope, so nonchalantly paraded in popular and even technical accounts of quantum theory, actively obscures rather than expresses what is truly revolutionary about it.
Quantum mechanics is in a certain sense not hard at all. It is baffling and surprising, and right now you could say that it remains cognitively impenetrable. But that doesn't mean it is hard in the way that car maintenance or learning Chinese is hard (I speak with bitter experience of both). Plenty of scientists find the theory easy enough to accept and master and use.
Rather than insisting on its difficulty, we might better regard it as a beguiling, maddening, even amusing gauntlet thrown down to challenge the imagination.
For that is indeed what is challenged. I suspect we are, in the wider cultural context, finally beginning to appreciate this. Artists, writers, poets and playwrights have started to imbibe and deploy ideas from quantum physics: see, for instance, plays such as Tom Stoppard's Hapgood and Michael Frayn's Copenhagen, and novels such as Jeanette Winterson's Gut Symmetries and Audrey Niffenegger's The Time Traveler's Wife. We can argue about how accurately or aptly these writers appropriate the scientific ideas, but it is right that there should be imaginative responses to quantum mechanics, because it is quite possible that only an imagination sufficiently broad and liberated will come close to articulating what it is about.
There's no doubt that the world described by quantum mechanics defies our intuitions. But 'weird' is not a particularly useful way to talk about it, since that world is also our world. We now have a fairly good, albeit still incomplete, account of how the world familiar to us, with objects having well-defined properties and positions that don't depend on how we choose to measure them, emerges from the quantum world. This 'classical' world is, in other words, a special case of quantum theory, not something distinct from it. If anything deserves to be called weird, it is us.
* * *
Here are the most common reasons for calling quantum mechanics weird. We're told it says that:
• Quantum objects can be both waves and particles. This is wave-particle duality.
• Quantum objects can be in more than one state at once: they can be both here and there, say. This is called superposition.
• You can't simultaneously know exactly two properties of a quantum object. This is Heisenberg's uncertainty principle.
• Quantum objects can affect one another instantly over huge distances: so-called 'spooky action at a distance'. This arises from the phenomenon called entanglement.
• You can't measure anything without disturbing it, so the human observer can't be excluded from the theory: it becomes unavoidably subjective.
• Everything that can possibly happen does happen. There are two separate reasons for this claim. One is rooted in the (uncontroversial) theory called quantum electrodynamics that Feynman and others formulated. The other comes from the (extremely controversial) 'Many Worlds Interpretation' of quantum mechanics.
Yet quantum mechanics says none of these things. In fact, quantum mechanics doesn't say anything about 'how things are'. It tells us what to expect when we conduct particular experiments. All of the claims above are nothing but interpretations laid on top of the theory. I will ask to what extent they are good interpretations (and try to give at least a flavour of what 'interpretation' might mean) – but I will say right now that none of them is a very good interpretation and some are highly misleading.
The question is whether we can do any better. Regardless of the answer, we are surely being fed too narrow and too stale a diet. The conventional catalogue of images, metaphors and 'explanations' is not only clichéd but risks masking how profoundly quantum mechanics confounds our expectations.
It's understandable that this is so. We can hardly talk about quantum theory at all unless we find stories to tell about it: metaphors that offer the mind purchase on such slippery ground. But too often these stories and metaphors are then mistaken for the way things are. The reason we can express them at all is that they are couched in terms of the quotidian: the quantum rules are shoehorned into the familiar concepts of our everyday world. But that is precisely where they no longer seem to fit.
* * *
It's very peculiar that a scientific theory should demand interpretation at all. Usually in science, theory and interpretation go together in a relatively transparent way. Certainly a theory might have implications that are not obvious and need spelling out, but the basic meaning is apparent at once.
Take Charles Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection. The objects to which it refers – organisms and species – are relatively unambiguous (if actually a little challenging to make precise), and it's clear what the theory says about how they evolve. This evolution depends on two ingredients: random, inheritable mutations in traits; and competition for limited resources that gives a reproductive advantage to individuals with certain variants of a trait. How this idea plays out in practice – how it translates to the genetic level, how it is affected by different population sizes or different mutation rates, and so on – is really rather complex, and even now not all of it is fully worked out. But we don't struggle to understand what the theory means. We can write down the ingredients and implications of the theory in everyday words, and there is nothing more that needs to be said.
Feynman seemed to feel that it was impossible and even pointless to attempt anything comparable for quantum mechanics:
We can't pretend to understand it since it affronts all our commonsense notions. The best we can do is to describe what happens in mathematics, in equations, and that's very difficult. What is even harder is trying to decide what the equations mean. That's the hardest thing of all.
Most users don't worry too much about these puzzles. In the words of the physicist David Mermin of Cornell University, they 'shut up and calculate'. For many decades quantum theory was regarded primarily as a mathematical description of phenomenal accuracy and reliability, capable of explaining the shapes and behaviours of molecules, the workings of electronic transistors, the colours of nature and the laws of optics, and a whole lot else. It would be routinely described as 'the theory of the atomic world': an account of what the world is like at the tiniest scales we can access with microscopes.
Talking about the interpretation of quantum mechanics was, on the other hand, a parlour game suitable only for grandees in the twilight of their career, or idle discussion over a beer. Or worse: only a few decades ago, professing a serious interest in the topic could be tantamount to career suicide for a young physicist. Only a handful of scientists and philosophers, idiosyncratically if not plain crankily, insisted on caring about the answer. Many researchers would shrug or roll their eyes when the 'meaning' of quantum mechanics came up; some still do. 'Ah, nobody understands it anyway!'
How different this is from the attitude of Albert Einstein, Niels Bohr and their contemporaries, for whom grappling with the apparent oddness of the theory became almost an obsession. For them, the meaning mattered intensely. In 1998 the American physicist John Wheeler, a pioneer of modern quantum theory, lamented the loss of the 'desperate puzzlement' that was in the air in the 1930s. 'I want to recapture that feeling for all, even if it is my last act on Earth', Wheeler said.
Wheeler may indeed have had some considerable influence in making this deviant tendency become permissible again, even fashionable. The discussion of options and interpretations and meanings may no longer have to remain a matter of personal preference or abstract philosophizing, and if we can't say what quantum mechanics means, we can now at least say more clearly and precisely what it does not mean.
This re-engagement with 'quantum meaning' comes partly because we can now do experiments to probe foundational issues that were previously expressed as mere thought experiments and considered to be on the border of metaphysics: a mode of thinking that, for better or worse, many scientists disdain. We can now put quantum paradoxes and puzzles to the test – including the most famous of them all, Schrödinger's cat.
These experiments are among the most ingenious ever devised. Often they can be done on a benchtop with relatively inexpensive equipment – lasers, lenses, mirrors – yet they are extraordinary feats to equal anything in the realm of Big Science. They involve capturing and manipulating atoms, electrons or packets of light, perhaps one at a time, and subjecting them to the most precise examination. Some experiments are done in outer space to avoid the complications introduced by gravity. Some are done at temperatures colder than the void between the stars. They might create completely new states of matter. They enable a kind of 'teleportation'; they challenge Werner Heisenberg's view of uncertainty; they suggest that causation can flow both forwards and backwards in time or be scrambled entirely. They are beginning to peel back the veil and show us what, if anything, lies beneath the blandly reassuring yet mercurial equations of quantum mechanics.
Such work is already winning Nobel Prizes, and will win more. What it tells us above all else is very clear: the apparent oddness, the paradoxes and puzzles of quantum mechanics, are real. We cannot hope to understand how the world is made up unless we grapple with them.
Perhaps most excitingly of all, because we can now do experiments that exploit quantum effects to make possible what sounds as though it should be impossible, we can put those tricks to work. We are inventing quantum technologies that can manipulate information in unprecedented ways, transmit secure information that cannot be read surreptitiously by eavesdroppers, or perform calculations that are far beyond the reach of ordinary computers. In this way more than any other, we will all soon have to confront the fact that quantum mechanics is not some weirdness buried in remote, invisible aspects of the world, but is our current best shot at uncovering the laws of nature, with consequences that happen right in front of us.
What has emerged most strongly from this work on the fundamental aspects of quantum theory over the past decade or two is that it is not a theory about particles and waves, discreteness or uncertainty or fuzziness. It is a theory about information. This new perspective gives the theory a far more profound prospect than do pictures of 'things behaving weirdly'. Quantum mechanics seems to be about what we can reasonably call a view of reality. More even than a question of 'what can and can't be known', it asks what a theory of knowability can look like.
(Continues...)Excerpted from Beyond Weird by Philip Ball. Copyright © 2018 Philip Ball. Excerpted by permission of The University of Chicago Press.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.
Product details
- ASIN : B07H9HNDYL
- Publisher : The University of Chicago Press; First edition (October 18, 2018)
- Publication date : October 18, 2018
- Language : English
- File size : 9.3 MB
- Text-to-Speech : Enabled
- Screen Reader : Supported
- Enhanced typesetting : Enabled
- X-Ray : Not Enabled
- Word Wise : Enabled
- Print length : 370 pages
- Best Sellers Rank: #85,612 in Kindle Store (See Top 100 in Kindle Store)
- #16 in Quantum Theory (Kindle Store)
- #69 in Science History & Philosophy
- #73 in Quantum Theory (Books)
- Customer Reviews:
About the author

Discover more of the author’s books, see similar authors, read book recommendations and more.
Customer reviews
Customer Reviews, including Product Star Ratings help customers to learn more about the product and decide whether it is the right product for them.
To calculate the overall star rating and percentage breakdown by star, we don’t use a simple average. Instead, our system considers things like how recent a review is and if the reviewer bought the item on Amazon. It also analyzed reviews to verify trustworthiness.
Learn more how customers reviews work on AmazonCustomers say
Customers find the book provides a wonderful introduction to various interpretations of quantum mechanics, with one review highlighting its lucid descriptions of key thought experiments. The writing style receives mixed feedback - while some praise its great easy-to-read style, others find it difficult to understand. The content receives mixed reactions, with one customer describing it as a deep dive into a difficult subject. Customers appreciate the comprehensive bibliography, with one noting it includes hundreds of quote-worthy phrases.
AI-generated from the text of customer reviews
Select to learn more
Customers appreciate the book's explanations of quantum mechanics, particularly its introduction to various interpretations and thought experiments.
"...He describes an informational approach to QM and why it is seen as potentially fruitful given the peculiarities and limitations of types of..." Read more
"I very much enjoyed the book; it was well researched and well written...." Read more
"I found Philip Ball's book to be an excellent discussion of how difficult it is to reconcile QM with our ordinary perception of the physical world..." Read more
"...In short, it is a wonderful introduction into the emerging perspectives on Quantum Mechanics and how it connects to our Physical realities...." Read more
Customers find the book enjoyable, with one describing it as a life-changing read.
"...It is an ideas book in which Ball provides the reader with an excellent account of the state of play as of 2018...." Read more
"I very much enjoyed the book; it was well researched and well written...." Read more
"...I enjoyed his book...." Read more
"...It is revolutionary. It is masterful. If you want to grok quantum mechanics, this is the book to get. I'm sorry I just found it now." Read more
Customers appreciate the book's comprehensive bibliography, with one mentioning it includes hundreds of quote-worthy phrases.
"...The book comes with a comprehensive bibliography which appears to be useful. It also has a good index...." Read more
"...Great reading lists across the philosophy of physics can be found by Googling ‘David Wallace USC’ and going to his website...." Read more
"...His book is full of hundreds of quote worthy phrases and unique ways of looking at quantum mechanics that I've not read anywhere else...." Read more
"Great intro into the topic equipping the reader this an excellent overview of what is known and unknown on quantum mechanics...." Read more
Customers have mixed opinions about the writing style of the book, with some praising its great easy-to-read style and concise prose, while others find it difficult to understand and criticize its unnecessarily obscure vocabulary.
"This is a review of the Kindle edition of “Beyond Weird”, the format was easy to read...." Read more
"I very much enjoyed the book; it was well researched and well written...." Read more
"...The concepts are difficult to grasp and understand but it is the same with all other books about QM...." Read more
"...Wallace’s reading lists of books and articles are very thorough and evenhanded, covering the spectrum of interpretations, although in fairness he..." Read more
Customers have mixed reactions to the book's content, with some finding it deep and novel, while others describe it as filled with seeming paradoxes and unrealities.
"...The book contains no mathematics or equations. It is an ideas book in which Ball provides the reader with an excellent account of the state of play..." Read more
"...Quantum mechanics is a fraught and difficult topic. This book adds hubris, unnecessarily obscure vocabulary and intentionally convoluted language..." Read more
"...work received five stars because, to this reader at least, it is entirely unique - far different from any prior learning experience...." Read more
"...through a field of physics that's interesting but filled with seeming paradoxes and unrealities...." Read more
Top reviews from the United States
There was a problem filtering reviews. Please reload the page.
- Reviewed in the United States on February 28, 2019This is a review of the Kindle edition of “Beyond Weird”, the format was easy to read.
The book comes with a comprehensive bibliography which appears to be useful. It also has a good index.
I imagine that the book will appeal to students and educated laymen alike.
I found it absorbing and interesting. Hence the 5 stars. I will be rereading it and following up on some items in the bibliography.
Firstly, this is not about how quantum mechanics is weirder than you ever thought. If you don’t know quantum mechanics (QM) is weird, it would be a good idea to introduce yourself to the history of the subject; you will see why It has this reputation.
Neither is this a book from which you might teach yourself QM. You should seek out another if that is what you need. The book contains no mathematics or equations. It is an ideas book in which Ball provides the reader with an excellent account of the state of play as of 2018. I use the words “complex Hilbert space” in a quote from the book below. It is neither necessary to know what a complex Hilbert space is to read the book (or understand my review!) nor is it the case that if you know what this is then the book is a waste of time for you.
Bohr and Einstein could not agree on what, if any reality underlay QM. It may be tempting (justifiably so) to give up, abandon further inquiry and dismiss QM as “weird”. After all, it remains true that attending “any meeting about the fundamental principles of quantum mechanics is like being in a holy city in great tumult. You will find all the religions with all their priests pitted in holy war”. The priests agree on the foundational scriptures, but they diverge on the interpretation. The experts are not of one mind. Ball invites us to go “Beyond” our concern with weirdness and bring ourselves up to date with current thinking about what the theory means. What underlying reality if any, does Schrödinger’s equation describe or even hint at?
Paradoxes which have illuminated difficulties with the subject have been with us for many years. Schrödinger's Cat (is it, could it be, both dead and alive?) and the EPR paradox (does “quantum entanglement” entail instantaneous action at a distance, breaking relativity?) are amongst the conceptually difficult ideas tackled here.
Interpretations of QM are explained and evaluated. We are taken through Bohr's (the Schrödinger equation tells us all that can be known) Everett and Deutsch's (many worlds interpretation), Qbism (an even stronger reliance Schrödinger than Bohr) and others. Currently, attempts are being made to find satisfying axiomatic foundations; some are described here. The motivation behind this can be appreciated if we compare an example of a “standard” set for QM like:
“1. For every system there is a complex Hilbert space H.
2. States of the system correspond to projection operators onto H.
3. Those things that are observable somehow correspond to the eigenprojectors of Hermitian operators.
4. Isolated systems evolve according to the Schrödinger equation.”
with the laws of motion underlying Newtonian mechanics:
“1. Every object keeps moving at the same speed if no force is applied to it. If it is still to begin with, it stays still.
2. If a force is applied to an object, it accelerates in direct proportion to that force, and in the direction of that force.”
3. For every force that one body exerts on another, the other body exerts an equal force back in the opposite direction.”
Ball points out that given the difference in the language in the two sets of axioms, it is not surprising that there is a push for a quantum reconstruction.
He describes an informational approach to QM and why it is seen as potentially fruitful given the peculiarities and limitations of types of information available from quantum systems.
I get the impression that the informational approach is his favourite. A substantial minority of practitioners in the field still favour Bohr's view. Ball is harshest with the many worlds interpretation.
To repeat, I found this to be an excellent survey which has equiped me to venture deeper into the alleyways of that tumultuous city, listen to the priests and perhaps form an opinion of my own on the merits of their competing interpretations.
- Reviewed in the United States on April 23, 2024I very much enjoyed the book; it was well researched and well written. What I didn’t like was that Ball failed to consider what I believe to be the best explanation for the seeming weirdness of quantum mechanics: Experimental data is being interpreted within the overly simplistic context of materialism/physicalism rather than within the context of Platonic realism.
Admittedly materialism/physicalism is by far and away the most popular ontology (worldview) among scientists and philosophers of science. While it might not seem reasonable to replace materialism/physicalism based solely on the explanatory challenges posed by quantum mechanics there are a number of other explanatory challenges in other fields that might justify a new ontology.
For example, on page 124 Ball writes: “Sure, you can ask questions about what is ‘really going on’, or about the mind-body problem or free will - but these are issues for philosophy, not physics.”
Is it not possible that the mind-body problem and free will go unresolved because they are impossible to resolve within the context of materialism/physicalism?
I would maintain that a new ontology should address as many outstanding explanatory challenges as possible with the minimum number of ontological commitments. It must also include falsification and/or verification criteria if it is to have any chance of being accepted by the greater scientific community.
While not mentioned by Ball, the fields of medicine and experimental psychology also face difficult explanatory challenges.
For 75 years placebo testing has been a required component of all drug trials. How it works is unknown but the consensus is that it does work.
In experimental psychology a 2011 paper by Daryl Bem demonstrated the reality of precognition; his work has since been replicated by other labs. Retrocausation (an event in the future being the source of information received in the present) has been put forth as an explanation by defenders of materialism/physicalism. In subsequent research (Mossbridge and Ridan, 2018) it was shown that precognitive information is not about the future but about the most probable future. If retrocausation is to explain probabilistic precognition it would mean that an event that might not even take place in the future was the source of the precognitive information that was received in the present - this strikes me as magical thinking.
The most basic question that an ontology must address is: How many realms are there?
While Occam’s razor would suggest that “one” would be the best answer I would maintain that our shared reality is of such complexity that a single realm is not adequate to address all explanatory challenges.
What views of reality are evinced by the scientific data? I maintain that science evinces at least three separate and distinct views of reality:
1. The data associated with classical physics evinces a macro view of reality that is characterized by determinism.
2. The data associated with quantum physics evinces a micro view of reality that is characterized by indeterminism.
3. The data associated with the social sciences evinces multiple concurrent mental views of reality characterized by both self awareness and self determination.
It is difficult to explain how a single realm could give rise to all three views of reality; assigning each view to its own ontological realm would seem to be an option worth considering. This is exactly what Platonic realism does: the macro view can be attributed to Plato’s realm of being; the micro view can be attributed to Plato’s realm of becoming; the mental views can be attributed to Plato’s realm of the soul.
While Plato’s writings in and of themselves are clearly not adequate to address the explanatory requirements of modern science I believe that they can provide a foundation on which the ideas of others may be interpreted.
One such idea can be found in a 1989 paper by John Archibald Wheeler titled "Information, Physics, Quantum: The Search For Links" where Wheeler wrote:
"To endlessness no alternative is evident but loop, such a loop as this: Physics gives rise to observer-participancy; observer-participancy gives rise to information; and information gives rise to physics." (pp. 313-314)
While Wheeler intended that this process be grounded by materialism/physicalism, I do not see materialism/physicalism as being adequate for the following reasons:
1. The information needed to give rise to physics is not to be found in the natural universe.
2. The mechanism for consolidating the observer-participants input is not to be found in the natural universe.
When interpreted within the context of Platonic realism, however, both of these can be said to reside in Plato’s expanded realm of being.
In Plato’s ontology it is the demiurge that is said to give rise to the physical universe. Could this not be consistent with a process in the realm of being that reifies a digital image stored in the realm of being so as to create a new instance of the universe in the realm of becoming?
In this Platonic interpretation of quantum mechanics the laws of classical physics would be said to describe processing within the realm of being whereas quantum theory would be said to describe the natural universe (the realm of becoming). This would in turn give rise to the startling conclusion that gravity is not a force in the natural universe but rather an algorithm in the realm of being. Should this be the case it would mean that:
1. There will never be a fully satisfactory theory of quantum gravity for the simple reasons that quantum gravity does not exist.
2. The graviton will never be detected because quantum gravity does not exist.
3. The weak interactive massive particle (WIMP) will never be detected because dark matter does not exist.
4. The hierarchy problem in particle physics does not exist.
How does this enhanced Platonic realism address the explanatory challenges posed by the placebo effect and probabilistic precognition?
The placebo effect requires one to explain how the mind can be the cause of changes to the body. In my proposed enhanced Platonic realism it is information that flows from the mind (located in the realm of the soul) to the realm of being where it causes the reification process to select a different digital image of the universe for subsequent reification.
Probabilistic precognition is explained by the presence in the realm of being of multiple digital images of the universe - only a proper subset of which are ever selected for reification.
Top reviews from other countries
- GlenReviewed in Australia on July 28, 2019
5.0 out of 5 stars Readable explanation
A good conceptual coverage of quantum physics plus an oversight of “What next”. All a bit challenging and mind boggling.
- ElenaReviewed in Canada on January 17, 2025
5.0 out of 5 stars Amazing book
Amazing book, great to read yourself and then pass it on to a friend or a kid. Books like these are wonderful because they're very approachable and anyone can read them, and yet you learn about latest scientific discoveries. Fascinating book! Also makes a great gift for your nerdy friends :)
- Guy AnthonyReviewed in the United Kingdom on May 23, 2018
5.0 out of 5 stars The antidote for clichéd thinking about quantum theory
I love this book. It's a stunning, judicious investigation of quantum theory and many of its key interpretations. As an interested non-scientist, I've read several books on the subject, and this was refreshing on many levels. I found several of my beliefs about QT promptly opened up and dismantled, as PB propounds ways of understanding quantum phenomena that eschew the common tropes of thinking about QT. I liked the way PB explored the implications of various interpretations of QT for big philosophical questions about reality, knowledge and our interactions with the world. PB writes so clearly, and thoughtfully about the mind-bending quantum world and yet points, convincingly IMO, to how there needn't be any contradiction to what we're familiar with in the 'classical' world, so long as we are willing to accept the particular kind of conditional knowledge suggested by the outcomes of experiments into quantum objects. This is the book about quantum theory / mechanics I would recommend as a must-read.
- DFM41Reviewed in Italy on March 15, 2022
5.0 out of 5 stars Quantum Physics
A readable and knowledgeable introduction to the "weirdness" of quantum physics.
- SanthanaReviewed in India on February 1, 2019
5.0 out of 5 stars For the love(rs) of physics..
A book that surprises by its gripping tale and its 'quantum' of insights around a whole range of topics a lot of us would have read between 10-12th class Physics - from Max Planck's work on black body radiation, De Broglie's wave-particle duality, double slit experiment (Thomas Young),...... and Chemistry - Radioactive decay (C14 to N14), Quantum numbers (principal, azimuthal, magnetic and spin), Pauli's exclusion principle... And a whole range of distantly familiar topics.. Building into a climax of logical thought experiments around the mysterious world of quanta, and the limits of reason.. (as it stands today)... A classic on quantum physics for commoners... Couldn't get my hands on the hardcover version and so, Kindled it... Unputdownable 👍🏼